Thursday, April 28, 2022

Punishment

Since all vices are of bodily origin, it is possible for interference upon the body to correct vices. Such interference is punishment; an act intended to do this is an act of punishment. The successful correction of vices is sometimes called the spiritual welfare of the punished.

Since we can only know vices through evil acts, we can only punish the guilty. The threat of punishments, however, may help correct vices in those yet innocent; such threats are perfectly reasonable, and this secondary correction is deterrence.

Other acts may be materially the same with an act of punishment, such as restitution for theft or injury, the protection of society through incapacitation of the evildoer, or the quelling of the public’s anger at him. But they are not formally the same;[1] the act is only punishment insofar as it is understood through the foregoing definition.

Threats of punishment usually attempt to correct vices by threatening such a measure of pain, or of privation of pleasure, as would be proportionate to the evil done, in the sense that a threatened person’s sensitive desires will be affected by the threat of punishment in such a way as to neutralize the influence of his vices, possibly permanently. This method of determining the measure of punishment is the proper notion of retribution;[2] it is subordinate to deterrence, since the punishment itself is only an aid to it insofar as it makes such a threat credible.

Sometimes, the acts of punishment themselves are intended to correct vices, by affecting the evildoer’s mind in accordance with a particular understanding of psychology. This method of determining the measure of punishment is that which is called rehabilitation or reformation.

All methods of determining the measure of punishments are doubtful, with regard to their effectiveness at correcting vice. Proportionality is a tenuous notion which can never be understood with precision; and in most cases, the science of psychology is not yet advanced enough to have a distinct understanding of reformation.

The people usually have a vague understanding of retribution, and no understanding at all of reformation; so, it is best to avoid punishments which, when known by the public, will appear to them to be disproportionately grave. Any measure beyond their sense of proportion will not seem to be punishment, but mere unjust abuse.

Punishments may be divided into coercive and uncoercive punishments.[3] Coercive punishments may only be exacted by a legitimate state, because they directly interfere with the person or property of the punished, which is an infringement when done by those without authority. All other acts of punishment are uncoercive.

Some evil acts may not indicate vices in the agents who committed them, when there is reason to believe that the sensitive desire which motivated the act was caused by a circumstance which was peculiar to the particular act. In such cases, it is rational for the state to exercise mercy, which is to say, to not punish, and waive its right to punish. It may still rationally punish the acts, however, in order to maintain the power of deterrence in the threats of law.[4]

Since coercive punishments are necessarily detrimental to the bodily welfare of the punished,[5] and therefore, necessarily, to the general welfare, insofar as it is known; and since the effectiveness of all punishments, in general, at improving the spiritual welfare of the punished is doubtful; it appears that coercive punishments should only be applied to crimes against person and property, which are themselves detrimental to the general welfare, insofar as it is known. Even then, mercy should be exercised whenever it may be safely and rationally exercised.

Catholics should believe, however, that no coercive punishments should be given to any crimes, since there are no legitimate states.

Notes

[1] The following examples may make this clearer to the uninstructed.

If a thief repents and returns what he stole, restitution has been made to the victim, but no punishment has been exacted.

If I expel a man from my community because I believe that his mental condition will make him prone to dangerous acts, I have protected my community by removing the dangerous man and making him incapable of such acts; but I have not punished him, since I did not know him to be vicious.

If society is put under the convincing illusion that a man has been punished, their avenging sentiments are quelled, but no punishment has been actually given to the man.

If I announce that, after the punishment of this last person, the law forbidding his act will be abolished, such that no one will be punished for it anymore, then the punishment will not deter, since deterrence is actually a function of the threat of punishment, which the punishment only serves to make believable.

[2] Although the earlier mentioned idea, of quelling the public’s vengeful passions, is often called retribution, all defenses of retribution make it something independent of that, and closely tied to proportionality; so that I believe that I have assigned the name correctly.

I believe that there is no other intelligible way for a punishment to be proportionate to a crime.

[3] I almost called them “punishments of law” and “punishments of opinion”, following a division from J.S. Mill, On Liberty, §1. I might still do that in some places for rhetorical effect, but for technical purposes, Mill’s nomenclature may be misleading, since uncoercive punishments might not consist merely in voicing opinions about the punished, but also in depriving them of gifts, of access to certain private locations which they do not own, and of certain business relationships.

[4] The most common reasons to doubt the presence of vice are usually inscribed into law as universal exceptions to its application, as in cases of insanity or duress. Mercy only pertains to unexcepted cases.

[5] Bodily welfare, or simply welfare, is the ability to fulfill desires, as may be contrasted with spiritual welfare, which was defined just earlier. Violations of private property, including self-ownership, necessarily deprive a human being of the ability to fulfill his desire to continue to control the property, which is a desire that he demonstrated through his actions, since if he did not have this desire, he would give the property away. Violations of contract are also detrimental to welfare, insofar as they are violations of property. The general welfare is the bodily welfare of the entire society.

Tuesday, April 26, 2022

Sexual morality

Since human beings reproduce sexually, the natural-law ethical doctrines regarding the use of their reproductive powers may be termed sexual morality. This blog post outlines natural sexual morality in nine propositions, which are expounded upon.

1. The division of sexual acts

Proposition 1 — Sexual acts may be divided into the entelechic and the antiphysical.

All acts which make use of the reproductive powers are sexual acts. Sexual acts which make use of the reproductive powers in accordance with their natural end, which is reproduction, shall be called entelechic. Sexual acts which make use of the reproductive powers in a way contrary to their natural end shall be called antiphysical.

Entelechic sexual acts are sometimes called natural, reproductive, or rightly-ordered. These names are not used here, to avoid confusion with other senses of those words. Sometimes, only entelechic sexual acts are called properly sexual acts, which makes enough sense, but that nomenclature seems to give me no short name for other uses of the reproductive powers.

Antiphysical sexual acts are sometimes called unnatural, unreproductivedisordered, or perverted. These names are not used here, to avoid confusion with other senses of those words. The name antinatural is avoided because it mixes Greek and Latin roots, and because antiphysical was preferred by Symonds.

2. Entelechic sexual acts

Proposition 2 — Marriage is defined as a heterotelic, voluntary relationship, oriented to the production and rearing of children.

This is a reiteration of the doctrine which was stated in the anthropology. Here, I shall only reiterate the definitions of the components of the definition.

A relationship is defined as the fact of two human beings seeking the same end ‘coordinately’, i.e., by means of at least one of them being allowed by right, in certain conditions, to control property which the other owns.

A voluntary relationship is a relationship which is entered into by the consent of all parties. These are contrasted with innate relationships, into which someone may enter by being born; no one can be born into marriage.

A heterotelic relationship is a relationship that seeks some particular good. Marriage is definitely such a relationship, since it seeks the production and rearing of children. These last terms are assumed to be well-understood.

Proposition 3 — Entelechic sexual acts are only good when performed within a marriage.

A sexual act is performed within a marriage when it is done between persons who are married to each other.

Since entelechic sexual acts are ordered to reproduction, they are performed irrationally when the agents are persons who do not desire to reproduce. Since producing children places them under the responsibility of the parents, it is irrational to desire to produce children without desiring to rear them.

Therefore, in order for the entelechic sexual act to be good, both sexual agents must desire both to produce and to rear children. Since parents have authority over the child, and must exercise this authority to such an extent in the child’s early years that the child’s body is effectively their property, the parents must either desire to rear the child coordinately or to enter into action conflicts. Since the latter desire is irrational, sexual agents must desire to marry, in order for their entelechic sexual act to be good.

It would be irrational to directly take part in another’s irrational act. Therefore, both sexual agents must ascertain, in order for the act to be good, that the other agent has the desire to produce and rear children coordinately. Since it is a voluntary relationship, the expression of this desire by both parties would initiate a marriage. Therefore, in order for an entelechic sexual act to be good, it must be performed within a marriage.

Proposition 4 — The natural law does not require that marriages be binary.

A binary relationship is a relationship between exactly two persons. Although monogamy is a salutary and laudable custom, it is nevertheless only a custom; nothing in human nature, as I understand it, requires it.

Proposition 5 — Marriage is, by nature, hierarchical.

A hierarchical society is a heterotelic relationship in which one person has decision-making priority over property owned by the society for as long as the relationship lasts.

The alternative would be equal, or democratic society, in which the property is owned in common, equally and without any such decision-making priority. Such common property is forbidden by the law of nature, since it frustrates the purpose of individual appropriation.

Nothing in human nature requires that the hierarchical head of the society be the father of the child rather than the mother. This is traditionally the case because fathers, besides being generally physically stronger, have traditionally been the primary, or only, source of income for the family, which gave them leverage to claim the headship.

The natural hierarchy in marriage gives the superior no right to boss the inferior around, either; by nature, he only has priority in decisions about the societal property of the marriage. The custom of wives being housewives, in particular, far from being required by reason, seems even to be detrimental to their well-being.

Proposition 6 — Marriage is, by nature, indissoluble, after it is consummated.

By consummation I mean the first entelechic sexual act performed within the marriage. By indissoluble I mean that an attempt to end a marriage would be an evil act.

Since marriage is constituted by the consent of both parties, it could only be ended if at least one of them ceased to desire to rear the children produced by their sexual acts. But this would be evil, given the responsibility of parents over children. This makes marriage indissoluble, once it has been consummated.

Married couples may desire to stop having any more sex, and to no longer have any more children; this does not end a  consummated marriage, since it remains that they have already performed an act which is ordered to reproduction. They still desire to rear, coordinately, any further children which their previous sexual acts may have caused to be produced, supposing that such a thing is possible; so the marriage stands.

Divorce, in our society, is generally desired to procure a second marriage, due to the custom of monogamy. Under the natural law, the so-called divorced person is simply married to both his first and his second spouse – see proposition 4 – in perpetuity. Our custom of alimony, for that matter, seems to be a recognition of a parent’s continuing responsibility for the children of his first marriage.

3. Antiphysical sexual acts

Proposition 7 — Antiphysical sexual acts are evil, in general.

Since antiphysical sexual acts constitute the use of a power in a way contrary to its natural end, their performance cannot be directly desired by reason. Therefore, they can only be directly desired by disordered passion; but the indulgence in such desires is the very nature of an evil act. So, antiphysical sexual acts are evil, in general.

Proposition 8 — Antiphysical sexual acts are justified when intended to secure the integral good of the agents.

By the integral good of the agents, I mean the same thing as their whole good, as human beings. For these acts to be justified means that they are good, but only because they are indirectly desired, as means to secure the integral good of the agents. The proposition is evident from the general doctrine that parts are subordinate to the whole; the reproductive powers are only one part of human beings.

Antiphysical sexual acts are intended to secure the integral good of an agent when they are intended to secure a human being’s use of his rational powers, as when done under duress, or as a treatment of mental illness.

Antiphysical sexual acts are also intended to secure the integral good of an agent when they are intended toward the good of an autotelic relationship, as when done to bring friends closer together.

4. Theological note

Proposition 9 — The Christian faith amends some of these propositions.

The foregoing has been an exercise in natural law ethics, done from my particular anthropology and metaphysics. Within the Christian religion, divine law may ordain stricter rules of conduct. In particular, the Christian religion raises marriage to the level of a sacrament, so that it is then called sacramental marriage; among other differences between natural and sacramental marriage, sacramental marriage is strictly monogamous, so that Proposition 4 does not apply to it.

Thursday, April 21, 2022

Mental classes

Soundness of understanding is connected with simplicity of manners, and leisure for intellectual cultivation: consequently, a distribution of property extremely unequal, is adverse to the most desirable state of man.

— William Godwin, Enquiry, Summary of Principles

There have been three social classes in history, more or less; belonging to each of them has its peculiar effects upon the intellectual life.

The lowest class, or the proletariat, is affected chiefly by the pressures of want. Bodily desires for such things as food and water make it difficult to think properly; they are wont to disregard the rules of philosophy and to structure all their thinking into a justification for such massive changes as would appear to them to save them from their misery. They are prone to support the error of enthusiasm: to attribute to art that which comes from nature.

The highest class, or the aristocracy, is affected chiefly in the opposite way; the great pleasures available to their luxurious condition are liable to be partaken of in excess. They are wont to disregard the rules of philosophy as well, and to structure all their thinking into a justification for their stability in their station, even beyond any usefulness it may have had. They are prone to support the error of superstition: to attribute to nature that which comes from art.

Only the middle class, or the bourgeoisie, are clear-sighted, objective truth-seekers. Being free from want and from excess, they will follow the rules of philosophy. The result is that they will favor the unhampered, undisturbed natural order, even when it is not useful to themselves. This is good political judgment.

Wednesday, April 20, 2022

Hume’s perversions

This post is not about salacious details of David Hume’s life, since I don’t know of any. It is about passages in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding which were quite tangential to his main arguments, but in which he portrayed the world in a false and dangerous way.

I have written this post while having only read the Enquiry, besides the first two parts of the Treatise; I plan to update it if I find relevant information when reading Hume’s other works and biographical details.

0. Contents

1. Contemplative life condemned
2. Scepticism a restraint upon passions
3. Sensible things clearer, and more distinct, than intelligible things
4. Reasoning more fallible than instinct
5. Notes

1. Contemplative life condemned

Hume begins section 5 of the Enquiry by speaking of “the passion for philosophy”. He correctly describes the temptation to use the methods of philosophy to give an appearance of reasonableness to our vices, that is, to “render our philosophy like that of Epictetus, and other Stoics, only a more refined system of selfishness, and reason ourselves out of all virtue, as well as social enjoyment.”

Here he already begins perverting things. While he does not say so in so many words, he apparently thinks that the Stoics are selfish because they thought that the “contemplative”, or “theoretical” life, was the superior kind. Hume, in section 1, had written about the active and contemplative life, and favored a “mixed kind of life as most suitable to the human race”. He had this reproach about the contemplative:

The mere philosopher is a character, which is commonly but little acceptable in the world, as being supposed to contribute nothing either to the advantage or pleasure of society; while he lives remote from communication with mankind, and is wrapped up in principles and notions equally remote from their comprehension. (§1¶5)

In section 1, he attributed those opinions to “the world”, and then afterwards said that the mixed life is favored by “nature”. But in section 5, after condemning the Stoics, he adds:

While we study with attention the vanity of human life, and turn all our thoughts towards the empty and transitory nature of riches and honours, we are, perhaps, all the while flattering our natural indolence, which, hating the bustle of the world, and drudgery of business, seeks a pretence of reason to give itself a full and uncontrolled indulgence. (§5¶1)

It seems clear, then, that Hume shares the opinion that he had attributed to mankind. The philosopher is not useful to the world; his researches really do “contribute nothing either to the advantage or pleasure of society”; and when he praises the contemplative life, he is merely flattering his lazy and selfish desire to retreat from useful business into the indulgence of his passion for science. 

Hume is not a hypocrite here, since he thinks, after all, that

the mere ignorant is still more despised [than the mere philosopher]; nor is any thing deemed a surer sign of an illiberal genius in an age and nation where the sciences flourish, than to be entirely destitute of all relish for those noble entertainments. (§1¶5)

But he leaves no doubt that he thinks of the sciences as mere “entertainments”, though “noble”; and he probably thinks that being “ignorant” is only despicable because of how it makes you less interesting when conversing in society. Knowledge has no inherent value apart from action, and the search for knowledge is indulgent when not subordinated to action, oriented to “the advantage or pleasure of society”.

Hume seems even to think that “riches and honours” ought not to be despised, since, after all, riches are a sign of industry when peacefully acquired – Hume was an economist –, and honours are bestowed by society upon those who are thought to serve its interest.

What sort of ethics are we left with here?

Hume probably thinks that “the interest of society” does not generally consist in the disinterested acquisition of knowledge, because of how the masses do not generally have “the passion for philosophy,” its “principles and notions” being far “remote from their comprehension”. This is why knowledge is regarded as, ideally, instrumental. But then, necessarily, the interest of society must consist in fleeting things.

The old proofs about the end of life remain unimpeachable. Wealth is unsuited to be the chief goal of one’s pursuits because it is a mere means to other things; honor, besides being only an effect of the good life, is generally given by the stupid masses, who do not know it when they see it. Bodily pleasure, in turn, is fleeting and movable, and at the mercy of fortune. Only knowledge is permanent and eternal, and virtue is identical with it.

Against these old notions, Hume has only this to say:

Man is a reasonable being; and as such, receives from science his proper food and nourishment: But so narrow are the bounds of human understanding, that little satisfaction can be hoped for in this particular, either from the extent or security of his acquisitions. (§1¶6)

We see, then, what his epistemology has done to his ethics. Hume thinks that philosophical knowledge is generally false; that all our thoughts are ultimately copied from sense impressions, and are only made general by our use of language; and therefore, that our beliefs consist entirely of probable inductive judgments about material things, which he rightly regards as fleeting, since they may be disproved by any new observations. Near the end of the Enquiry, of course, he famously made an exception for mathematics (§12¶27), but he made it arbitrarily,[1] and it clearly played no part in his ethics.[2]

Hume, of course, had no reason to think any of these things. The “copy principle” was entirely made up, and the rest of his notions clearly came from a failure to distinguish imagination from conceptual understanding; which, being a confusion of a bodily power with a spiritual one, is just as much the mark of a carnal man as his effective making of bodily pleasure into the end of human life.

2. Scepticism a restraint upon passions

In view of what was just shown about his ethics, Hume’s next perversion becomes much more ridiculous. He continues section 5 as follows:

There is, however, one species of philosophy which seems little liable to this inconvenience, and that because it strikes in with no disorderly passion of the human mind, nor can mingle itself with any natural affection or propensity; and that is the Academic or Sceptical philosophy. The academics always talk of doubt and suspense of judgement, of danger in hasty determinations, of confining to very narrow bounds the enquiries of the understanding, and of renouncing all speculations which lie not within the limits of common life and practice. Nothing, therefore, can be more contrary than such a philosophy to the supine indolence of the mind, its rash arrogance, its lofty pretensions, and its superstitious credulity. (§5¶1)

He has already begun perverting things by supposing that pride takes the form of a man being too confident in his judgment; it does not, and this is an old canard of the sceptics, who have ever tried to frame their scepticism as “epistemic humility”. But he continues:

Every passion is mortified by it, except the love of truth; and that passion never is, nor can be, carried to too high a degree. It is surprising, therefore, that this philosophy, which, in almost every instance, must be harmless and innocent, should be the subject of so much groundless reproach and obloquy. But, perhaps, the very circumstance which renders it so innocent is what chiefly exposes it to the public hatred and resentment. By flattering no irregular passion, it gains few partizans: By opposing so many vices and follies, it raises to itself abundance of enemies, who stigmatize it as libertine, profane, and irreligious. (§5¶1)

Now this is just ridiculous. Obviously the “love of truth”, if it be a passion, is the only passion mortified by scepticism, which tends ever to make people diffident in their pursuit of it, as Hume just acknowledged.[3] The love of truth is perfectly virtuous, of course, and it is precisely for stymieing it that scepticism is condemned.

Further, since it commonly takes the form of scepticism about ethical propositions, it is rather used in favor of every vice. Hume probably thinks that it cannot be used in this way, of course, as he wrote elsewhere about determinism:

Are such remote and uncertain speculations able to counterbalance the sentiments, which arise from the natural and immediate view of the objects? A man who is robbed of a considerable sum; does he find his vexation for the loss any wise diminished by these sublime reflections? Why then should his moral resentment against the crime be supposed incompatible with them? (§8¶35)

But plainly, the reason why scepticism is thought to be “libertine, profane, and irreligious” is that, if applied to religion and ethics, it removes from such “moral resentment” any pretense of being reasonable, and justified by the nature of things. If you wish to renounce reason and live as the beasts, you can do no better than to proclaim reason “infirm” and uncertain; such will be the judgment which you shall foster about all reproaches of your conduct.

3. Sensible things clearer, and more distinct, than intelligible things

Hume continues to present a perverted worldview in section 7, where he makes sensible things to be more sharply distinguished than intelligible ones:

The great advantage of the mathematical sciences above the moral consists in this, that the ideas of the former, being sensible, are always clear and determinate, the smallest distinction between them is immediately perceptible, and the same terms are still expressive of the same ideas, without ambiguity or variation. An oval is never mistaken for a circle, nor an hyperbola for an ellipsis. The isosceles and scalenum are distinguished by boundaries more exact than vice and virtue, right and wrong. If any term be defined in geometry, the mind readily, of itself, substitutes, on all occasions, the definition for the term defined: Or even when no definition is employed, the object itself may be presented to the senses, and by that means be steadily and clearly apprehended. But the finer sentiments of the mind, the operations of the understanding, the various agitations of the passions, though really in themselves distinct, easily escape us, when surveyed by reflection; nor is it in our power to recal the original object, as often as we have occasion to contemplate it. Ambiguity, by this means, is gradually introduced into our reasonings: Similar objects are readily taken to be the same: And the conclusion becomes at last very wide of the premises. (§7¶1)

Obviously the isosceles and scalenum are not distinguished more exactly “than vice and virtue, right and wrong”, which are contradictory opposites. While these triangles are usually defined as having equal and unequal sides respectively, the terms themselves are connected chiefly with sensible images. There is, accordingly, disagreement about whether the isosceles should be defined as having exactly two equal sides or at least two equal sides; and someone could, in theory, think that the essential property of the isosceles is that its “intriangle” has two equal sides, in which case there could be scalene isosceles triangles. This is why mathematical terms are conventional, and authors are free to use them in whatever ways they think are in accordance with the imagination of readers. There are, of course, educational benefits to defining them in particular ways; but each teacher may do as he thinks best. An oval may not be mistaken for a circle, nor an hyperbola for an ellipsis; but an oval may be mistaken for an ellipsis, until definitions are brought to bear.

Metaphysical and ethical terms, by contrast, are free from sensible images; there is generally no “original object” to recall. It is impossible to imagine vice and virtue in the abstract. So, the metaphysical reasoner is unable to create confusion by replacing images for concepts; he must think in terms of the definitions, and he can get nowhere by trying to use his imagination.

Accordingly, since it is impossible to think about metaphysics and ethics without substituting definitions, whereas such vague imaginations are sometimes useful in geometry, it follows that the sciences of quantity, and of sensible things generally, are more prone to ambiguity than metaphysics and ethics. And this is to be expected, given that they treat of objects which are so connected to our imprecise senses. Empiricism, which is always a pernicious vice, sometimes leads to a complete inversion of reality.

4. Reasoning more fallible than instinct

The final perversion of David Hume, by which he again exalts the body over the soul, is to claim that instincts operate more reliably than reason. His actual arguments are partly involved into this, since he claims that our process of inferring effects from causes is such an instinct:

I shall add, for a further confirmation of the foregoing theory, that, as this operation of the mind, by which we infer like effects from like causes, and vice versa, is so essential to the subsistence of all human creatures, it is not probable, that it could be trusted to the fallacious deductions of our reason, which is slow in its operations; appears not, in any degree, during the first years of infancy; and at best is, in every age and period of human life, extremely liable to error and mistake. It is more conformable to the ordinary wisdom of nature to secure so necessary an act of the mind, by some instinct or mechanical tendency, which may be infallible in its operations, may discover itself at the first appearance of life and thought, and may be independent of all the laboured deductions of the understanding. As nature has taught us the use of our limbs, without giving us the knowledge of the muscles and nerves, by which they are actuated; so has she implanted in us an instinct, which carries forward the thought in a correspondent course to that which she has established among external objects; though we are ignorant of those powers and forces, on which this regular course and succession of objects totally depends. (§5¶22)

We certainly do make such inferences somewhat automatically, and cannot explain the process by which we do them in great detail. This is no more proof that they are infra-rational than the same facts being true about all other inferences.

If we are to explain why the reasoning, that all men are mortal, and all philosophers are men, therefore all philosophers are mortal, is valid, we might say that it belongs to the barbara logical form. We cannot explain, however, why the barbara logical form is valid; this is knowledge which we certainly have from reason, but cannot express in very elaborate words.

The effect of Hume’s rhetoric here is to degrade reason. Reason always works infallibly when it works by itself; it just happens that, often, passions intrude upon it. Our instincts, by contrast, although they generally perform useful functions for our body, are frequently “fooled” by peculiar material circumstances for which our nature does not prepare us; and variously, a man may feel hunger when he is full, feel full when he is starving, or feel fear while he is safe. These circumstances are frequently manipulated for medicine or entertainment, as the last one is exploited by horror movies.

It may be that there is also an instinct for inferring effects from causes, since it does seem, as Hume points out in §9, that the brutes are capable of doing this. This would not seem to be beyond the power of mere bodily mechanism, since probable inductive judgments are necessarily imperfect with respect to deductions, and may require only mere images rather than true concepts. But this would certainly not be because “an operation of such immense consequence in life” cannot “be trusted to the uncertain process of reasoning and argumentation.” (§9¶5) If reason is not certain, nothing is.

5. Notes

[1] Hume explained his exception like this:

As the component parts of quantity and number are entirely similar, their relations become intricate and involved; and nothing can be more curious, as well as useful, than to trace, by a variety of mediums, their equality or inequality, through their different appearances. But as all other ideas are clearly distinct and different from each other, we can never advance farther, by our outmost scrutiny, than to observe this diversity, and, by an obvious reflection, pronounce one thing not to be another. (§12¶27)

Now, what the hell does the “component parts” being “entirely similar” have to do with anything? In particular, with being an object of demonstration? I can only think of this as a spurious justification, made up on the spot to explain how obviously successful mathematical demonstrations are.

[2] Bertrand Russell’s essay on The Study of Mathematics is a very useful comparison here. Russell was also inclined to empiricism, though not as thoroughly as Hume; and he also regarded mathematics as uniquely certain. After noting the unique certainty of mathematics, which is a “perpetual reproof” against “that kind of scepticism which abandons the pursuit of ideals because the road is arduous and the goal not certainly attainable”, he also noted how mathematics, since it is clearly practically useful, also allayed his thoughts, similar to Hume’s, that mere speculation is a vain and indulgent pursuit:

The effects of mathematics upon practical life, though they should not be regarded as the motive of our studies, may be used to answer a doubt to which the solitary student must always be liable. In a world so full of evil and suffering, retirement into the cloister of contemplation, to the enjoyment of delights which, however noble, must always be for the few only, cannot but appear as a somewhat selfish refusal to share the burden imposed upon others by accidents in which justice plays no part. Have any of us the right, we ask, to withdraw from present evils, to leave our fellow-men unaided, while we live a life which, though arduous and austere, is yet plainly good in its own nature? When these questions arise, the true answer is, no doubt, that some must keep alive the sacred fire, some must preserve, in every generation, the haunting vision which shadows forth the goal of so much striving. But when, as must sometimes occur, this answer seems too cold, when we are almost maddened by the spectacle of sorrows to which we bring no help, then we may reflect that indirectly the mathematician often does more for human happiness than any of his more practically active contemporaries. The history of science abundantly proves that a body of abstract propositions—even if, as in the case of conic sections, it remains two thousand years without effect upon daily life—may yet, at any moment, be used to cause a revolution in the habitual thoughts and occupations of every citizen. The use of steam and electricity—to take striking instances—is rendered possible only by mathematics. In the results of abstract thought the world possesses a capital of which the employment in enriching the common round has no hitherto discoverable limits. Nor does experience give any means of deciding what parts of mathematics will be found useful. Utility, therefore, can be only a consolation in moments of discouragement, not a guide in directing our studies.

The obvious practical usefulness of mathematics, which Hume had not mentioned, may have been a motivation for his arbitrary distinction of it. But of course, mathematics is only uniquely practical among demonstrative sciences to men such as these, who regard metaphysics as absurd, ethics as separate from it, and ethical inquiry as being ultimately an expression of inscrutable, and possibly idiosyncratic, emotions.

[3] If any one thinks that Hume does not think that scepticism makes someone generally diffident, but rather is merely directed against vicious “arrogance”, “pretension” and “credulity”, let him hear what Hume says of Berkeley’s arguments, in a footnote to the last section:

He professes, however, in his title-page (and undoubtedly with great truth) to have composed his book against the sceptics as well as against the atheists and free-thinkers. But that all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in reality, merely sceptical, appears from this, that they admit of no answer and produce no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and irresolution and confusion, which is the result of scepticism. (§12¶15, fn32)

While in the rest of the chapter he distinguishes the Pyrrhonian from the Academic sceptics, favoring the latter, here he does not. There is, at any rate, no possible way to deny that the Academic scepticism is harmful in the same way as the Pyrrhonian – by producing “irresolution and confusion”, and putting moral truths into doubt – although perhaps in a “mitigated” way, insofar as it admits of probabilities.

The harm of Academic scepticism might not even be so mitigated, however, since while the Pyrhonian sceptic “cannot expect, that his philosophy will have any constant influence on the mind”, (§12¶23) the Academic scepticism is capable of being “durable”. (§12¶24)

Hume thinks that the latter is “useful” besides durable, since it humbles the pride of “such dogmatical reasoners” as are “the greater part of mankind”; but it is a lie to claim that there is pride in dogmatic reasoning. It seems clear that a mitigated version of principles, by the prevalence of which “all human life must perish” (§12¶23), can only tend to destroy human life to a somewhat smaller extent.

Thursday, April 14, 2022

Thrasymachism

It is a mistake to ascribe to Thrasymachus the opinion that “might makes right”, if one means this in a prescriptive sense.

Thrasymachus made no distinction between what is called justice and “true” justice. He always used the word “justice” to refer to the former, that is, to what the word means in popular use. What is called justice, in turn, is defined by the rulers of states when they write their legislation (338e) – and they always write it in the way that they think is advantageous for themselves.

So, while he did say that “justice is nothing other than what is advantageous for the stronger” (338c), this is not to mean something good about the stronger, as though they deserved to rule for being superior – as, for instance, Callicles thought, in the Gorgias, 483c – but rather something bad about justice. Justice is a fool’s game, says Thrasymachus, because it is a set of arbitrary rules created by self-interested legislators. This is plainly true of what is called justice in every state, in each according to its laws.

Accordingly, he denied that justice is a virtue (348c), since it is not good for the one who has it, as a virtue should be; rather, it is good for the unjust, in which he includes foremost the legislators themselves (343c), but also anyone else who breaks the laws when it is good to do so. Good, that is, for himself.

Thrasymachus is important to the Republic because he sharply divides the metaphysical good – the object of correctly-formed rational desire – from the moral good, that is, the just. He believes, very soundly, that “the good is what all desire”, and what all people seek through their rational actions; he denies that justice is good. To seek the just is, often, to seek the bad, as a sacrifice for the good of others.

That is, in modern terms, Thrasymachus is a moral non-naturalist. The moral good is arbitrary and has no relation to what rational people desire to seek; the (morally) “good life” is not necessarily the life that you want, even if your passions and reason are in perfect order. To be just, you must sometimes be irrational, and purposely act against your best interest.

It is, of course, impossible to prove him wrong, and the dialogue never does. What it does, instead, is persuasively present the correct doctrine, that the metaphysical and the moral good are the same. It does so by presenting a fundamentally correct moral psychology by means of an elaborate poetical metaphor; in the metaphor, a man is compared to a city, and a just man to a wisely ruled city, and an unjust man to an unwisely ruled one. Since no one denies that the wisely ruled city is the good city, the good appear to be the just.

The state is merely man writ large; the metaphor cannot truly prove anything, but only show more clearly a concept of human nature which someone already holds. Not everyone will hold it in the first place; there are still non-naturalists, and there may always be.

Wednesday, April 13, 2022

Morality and ethics

This blog post is about the words “morality” and “ethics”.

The common root

Due to the long history of these words, and the continuing influence of old texts on their use, it is not irrelevant to begin with their etymology, which I will take from Wiktionary without bothering to check another source.

There we find that the word ethics comes, through French and Latin,

from Ancient Greek ἠθική (ēthikḗ), from ἠθικός (ēthikós, “of or for morals, moral, expressing character”), from ἦθος (êthos, “character, moral nature”).

A second definition of ἦθος given by the same website is “custom, habit”, as the LSJ also gives.

We also find that morality comes, through French, from Latin, that is, from

mōrālis (“relating to manners or morals”), from mōs (“manner, custom”).

Again, we find at the root a reference to “custom, habit, practice, usage, wont”.

Besides the fact that these Greek and Latin words were historically widely used to translate each other, then, we find that both of them relate ultimately to the same idea of “habits” or “customs”. This supports their common usage as synonyms of each other. Distinguishing them may have its merits, but the usage as synonyms is unimpeachable; I tend to follow it.

Habit, or custom

The fact that the idea at their root is as broad as “habits” or “customs” also explains, first, the very broad senses which the terms “ethics” and “moral philosophy” used to have up until early modernity. To cite just one source for this well-known fact:

To the modern reader the term ‘moral philosophy’ denotes the branch of philosophy that deals with ethics: a relatively small part of only one of the many departmental units in the modern university’s curriculum. In the eighteenth century the term was very much broader, embracing not only the whole of what we today classify as ‘philosophy’ but most of the subjects now included in a modern university’s divisions of social sciences and humanities.

Second, it explains why both terms are often thought to refer to something subjective, arbitrary, and positive, as opposed to universal, necessary, and normative. That is, to refer to any rules or methods of conduct that merely happen to be adopted by a person or a society. That is simply what custom is. This sense is best preserved in some related words: the word “mores” often refers to custom, and the word “ethic” often refers to any adopted principles of conduct.

This is why persons who believe in an “objective morality” often move away from either word and toward using the idea of law, as in the phrases “natural law” and “moral law”. However much the idea of law may be confused with arbitrary legislation, it certainly can never be confused with custom.

Suffixes

Obviously, using the terms as synonyms can only happen regarding a particular sense, referring to the set of moral rules which someone adopts. The different suffixes of these terms make them differently appropriate for use in other senses.

Ethics ends in -ics, which, in words from a Greek root, tends to form the name of a science. This is also seen in the words physics, genetics, economics, and aesthetics, for instance.

Since morality lacks such a suffix, the science of morality has to be either “moral philosophy” or “moral science”, and the length of these terms, as well as their variety, makes ethics the privileged term for the ethical science.

Morality ends in -ality, which often indicates a quality. And while both “moral” and “ethical” can refer to something being virtuous, the word ethicality does not see much use, unlike morality. So morality has a privileged use to refer to the quality of something’s being good or right, while ethics lacks the proper suffix for this.

Sources of beliefs

I present here a division of types of beliefs, according to their source, which I made up the other day. Some of them are compounds of other types, which I noted in square brackets.

(a) self-evident knowledge

Such are the laws of logic, such as the law of non-contradiction and the excluded middle. They are the source of the two first divisions.

Also self-evident is the fact that apparent things are knowable, which itself requires that they have the four causes.

(b) pure appearance

A second source of our beliefs is pure appearance, in which I include all of our sense perception, imagination, and memory.

(c) [a+b] knowledge of forms

Since apparent things are knowable, we must have knowledge of their immutable forms.

Besides the self-evident knowledge of the two first divisions, forms are the only objects of knowledge, properly speaking. Our experiences and memories are only known in a weaker sense.

(d) [c, imperfectly] probable inductive judgments

Sometimes, we cannot observe something well enough to understand it. But since the fact that apparent things are knowable requires that all of them have final causes, which is to say, operate according to necessary laws, inductions may be made – we can expect that often, similar appearances will follow each other in similar patterns. So, we can make judgments that they will follow each other in this way in a particular case, which is another source of our beliefs.

Such judgments are probable – they are not knowledge, properly speaking, but may nevertheless be highly certain.

(e) [d+b, or d+c] human faith

Our trust in reports and authority of other human persons is a compound of two probable judgments:

  • first, a probable judgment (d) that the person is not mistaken about having knowledge (c), or experience (b), of what he says;
  • second, a probable judgment (d) that the person is not lying about having knowledge (c), or experience (b), of what he says.

(f) [c+c] divine faith, in principle

In principle, our faith in God is produced similarly to human faith, but with the caveat that the two probable judgments are replaced with certain knowledge, since it is impossible that God could be lying or mistaken.

So, in principle, beliefs formed through divine faith are just as certain as knowledge of forms (c).

(g) [e+f, or b+f] divine faith, in practice

In practice, our beliefs of divine faith are not formed purely through faith in God, but through experiences (b) that we judge to be of divine origin, or through human reports (e) of such experiences. They are, therefore, as certain as those.

Of course, this is not to say they are terribly uncertain, if the reports come from trustworthy human persons, and the experiences were had in proper conditions.

(h) [d or c, mistaken for c] error, or conceit

If we mistake our probable inductive judgments (d) about something for true knowledge of its nature; or if we have true knowledge of a nature (c) but wrongly judge that a given apparent thing is of that nature, we are in error. Our belief, in such a case, may be called a conceit; Augustine called it opinion, but that word seems liable to mislead.

Saturday, April 9, 2022

Philosophical virtues

Corresponding to the three rules of philosophy, three philosophical virtues may be defined.

0. Contents

1. The virtues
1.1. Discernment, or clarity
1.1.1. Name
1.1.2. Precept
1.1.3. Models
1.2. Serenity, or tranquility
1.2.1. Name
1.2.2. Precept
1.2.3. Models
1.3. Integrity, or honesty
1.3.1. Name
1.3.2. Precept
1.3.3. Models
2. Their distinctness and uniqueness
3. Opposing vices

1. The virtues

1.1. Discernment, or clarity

The first rule enjoins, in philosophy, the persistent application of reason to all possible subjects. Accordingly, a virtue may be defined regarding the application of reason to life in general.

1.1.1. Name

This may be called discernment. The word appropriately conveys the first activity of reason, which is to divide and distinguish, and then to define. All failures of thought are failures to discern.

This may also be called clarity, since whatever is not thought about is left unclear, indistinct, confused.

1.1.2. Precept

The precept of discernment may be phrased as, “be rational” – or, for emphasis, “be rational about everything”. Since always acting rationally is, ultimately, the only rule of human conduct, another precept would be, “aim to be perfect”.

1.1.3. Models

The chief model of discernment is Socrates, who, in the Crito, was unwilling to save his life, unless he could be rationally convinced that it was right. Since it is also the virtue of clarity, exceptionally clear writers, such as Thomas Aquinas, may serve as virtuous models in relation to it – “how would Thomas think about this?”

1.2. Serenity, or tranquility

The second rule enjoins, in philosophy, the use of nothing other than reason; in particular, the senses and passions are to be kept at bay. Accordingly, a virtue may be defined regarding the control of the passions in life in general.

1.2.1. Name

This may be called serenity, or tranquility, which properly calls to mind such a person as is unperturbed by his environment. Any person who shows emotion is always acting immorally, and all moral errors are caused by the senses and passions.

1.2.2. Precept

The precept of serenity may be phrased as, “be impassive” – which is a perfectly good rendering of the Stoics’ apatheia. Of course, the problem is not so much with feeling emotions, as they sometimes seemed to imply, as with acting upon them. In view of an ultimate ideal, another precept could be, “aim to be impassible”.

1.2.3. Models

Anyone who met his death with patience is so far a model of serenity. Many Christian martyrs may be included here, but also Socrates again, and possibly Seneca. 

The thought of Stoic philosophers, in general, often emphasized tranquility and freedom from the passions, and may be kept in mind as a model, if not their lives themselves. Kant also emphasized this, and was once referred to as “the serene philosopher”. Others could be mentioned.

1.3. Integrity, or honesty

The third rule forbids, in philosophy, the use of abductive reasoning. Accordingly, a virtue may be defined forbidding, in life in general, the construction of reasons for predefined conclusions, which is rationalization, or deception.

1.3.1. Name

To prevent yourself from rationalizing is to have integrity; and to prevent yourself from lying is to have honesty. Both things are prevented if abductive reasoning is forbidden in life; and honesty carries the full meaning of integrity if one allows talk of “being honest with oneself”. To always act upon deduced reasons is to always act upon true ones.

1.3.2. Precept

The precept of integrity, put in a general way as the prohibition of contrived reasons, may be termed as, “be pure-hearted” – although the figure of the “pure heart” is not always well-understood, and sometimes implies naïveté, which is no virtue. In view of an ultimate ideal, another precept could be, “aim to be incorruptible”.

1.3.3. Models

The chief models of integrity are such persons as did what they thought was right, even when this went against all possible motives of regard to their welfare. This includes such preachers as, again, Socrates and the Christian martyrs.

But also, any philosopher who carried a difficult deduction to its end, even when this went against all common opinion, is worth mentioning here – Parmenides, for one, and possibly Spinoza. Of course, such persons are often accused of going against the multitude in favor of their passions, rather than their reason, so that choosing examples can be difficult.

2. Their distinctness and uniqueness

These virtues are not very distinct or unique. As defined, may be thought to be equivalent to the cardinal virtues. Discernment appears closest to prudence or courage, serenity to temperance, and integrity to justice.

Each of them is, in fact, equivalent to all four cardinal virtues; each one, if perfectly attained, would lead a man to the entirety of human perfection. For they enjoin nothing but the persistent and proper use of reason, which is the only rule of human conduct. Any moral error will break all of their precepts.

Which does not prevent their being equivalent to the cardinal virtues, of course, since “the unity of the virtues” is such a well-known concept. At any rate, since my approach here was not a standard one in ethics, I have picked new names.

This derivation of these virtues from the rules of philosophy, which in turn were derived from its definition, supports Socrates’ contention that the aim of the philosopher is to become like the gods – who are, of course, perfect, impassible, and incorruptible.

It also supports my best friend’s emphasis on what she called “intellectual virtue”, which she has always thought was the root of all virtue, though as the name implies, it is seen most clearly in expositions of one’s thoughts. I do not pretend this post to be expounding her doctrine, but I think that it seemed to agree with my own.

3. Opposing vices

The viciousness of a defect in discernment, serenity, or integrity is clear enough. I will give some names here. Persons lacking discernment may be thought to be unthinking or obscure; persons lacking serenity may be thought to be oversensitive or thin-skinned; persons lacking integrity may be thought to be dishonest or divided.

Since they are equivalent to the whole of virtue, I would contend that these virtues are pure perfections, and so, properly, there can be no excess of them. Still, they may appear to be beyond measure in some cases.

condescending attitude, of explaining things too much, may appear to be an excess of clarity; an insensitive or cruel attitude may appear to be an excess of tranquility or impassivity; and an indiscreet attitude, of revealing too much information, may appear to be an excess of honesty.

They are, of course, no such things. There is a difference between always having reasons, and always making them explicit; between disregarding emotions, and disregarding the real evils which cause them; between never lying, and never having secrets. Still, the popular association between these attitudes makes them bear mentioning here.

Wednesday, April 6, 2022

Principles of nature

This is a commentary on the Principles of Nature by Thomas Aquinas.

Since some things can be, although they are not, and some things now are; those which can be and are not are said to be potency, but those which already exist are said to be in act. But existence is twofold: one is essential existence or the substantial existence of a thing, for example man exists, and this is existence simpliciter. The other is accidental existence, for example man is white, and this is existence secundum quid. (¶1)

Thomas uses terms differently from how I do. As I said, it is impossible that “some things can be, although they are not”, since for non-being to be would be a contradiction. But some things can appear which do not, while others already appear. Some things, moreover, cannot appear, although they are – which is to say, they are unimaginable, but conceivable.

So, according to these differences, I will define my own terms as follows:

  • intelligible, imaginable, apparent: act
  • intelligible, imaginable, unapparent: potency
  • intelligible, unimaginable: form
  • unintelligible, imaginable, apparent: privation
  • unintelligible, imaginable, unapparent: disordered image
  • unintelligible, unimaginable: nothingness

According to my usage, forms are neither in potency nor in act, since potency and act only divide material things. The imagination is also capable of imagining appearances which cannot be understood, and I have no better name for those than “disordered images”, although this is new.

I will omit all paragraphs from this commentary which I believe can easily be interpreted according to my usage of the terms, and with which I would agree after this were done. Those are the majority, so this will be a short commentary, compared to the treatise itself.

In this way matter differs from subject because the subject is that which does not have existence by reason of something which comes to it, rather it has complete existence of itself (per se); just as man does not have existence through whiteness. But matter has existence by reason of what comes to it because, of itself, it has incomplete existence. Hence, simply speaking, the form gives existence to matter; the accident, however, does not give existence to the subject, rather the subject gives existence to the accident; although sometimes the one is used for the other, namely matter for subject and conversely. (¶4)

Again, existence here seems to mean appearance. But complete existence here seems to mean intelligible appearance, such as actual things – substances and accidents – have. In my terminology, I avoid using such imaginative language as of “giving” or “receiving” existence, as though existence is a ball which is passed around.

Besides this caveat about completeness, all unqualified instances of existence and being in this treatise seem to refer to appearance, as before.

From this it is plain, therefore, that there are three principles of nature: matter, form and privation. But these are not sufficient for generation. What is in potency cannot reduce itself to act; for example, the bronze which is in potency to being a statue cannot cause itself to be a statue, rather it needs an agent in order that the form of the statue might pass from potency to act. Neither can the form draw itself from potency to act. I mean the form of the thing generated which we say is the term of generation, because the form exists only in that which has been made to be. However, what is made is in the state of becoming as long as the thing is coming to be. Therefore it is necessary that besides the matter and form there be some principle which acts. This is called the efficient, moving or agent cause, or that whence the principle of motion is. Also, because, as Aristotle says in the second book of the Metaphysics, everything which acts acts only by intending something, it is necessary that there be some fourth thing, namely, that which is intended by the agent; and this is called the end. (¶18)

While the former parts of the work were properly demonstrated, the principles that “what is in potency cannot reduce itself to act”, and that “neither can the form draw itself from potency to act”, are simply stated and not proved. In lieu of proof, we get the statue example; but there is no reason to take this particular case as representative of all reality.

As I said in my metaphysics, I believe that efficient causes are implied by the understanding of apparent things because “something movable must be referred to the motions of [a moving] object in order that their particular arrangement in time and space may be understood”. I still believe that this is the proper concept of efficient causes, and I must regard Thomas’s explanation of them as merely conjectural. However, I will also define the agent as the efficient cause of a motion.

I have also not changed my definition of final causes from my metaphysics, which I mention because I am not sure whether Thomas’s definition of them is substantially different. Given a motion, however, I grant that its final cause may be said to be “intended by” its agent.

Element, on the other hand, is applied properly only to the causes of which the thing is composed, which are properly the materials. Moreover, it is not said of just any material cause, but of that one of which a thing is primarily composed; for example we do not say that the members of the body are the elements of man, because the members also are composed of other things; rather, we say that earth and water are the elements, because these are not composed of other bodies, but natural bodies are primarily composed of them. (¶24)

I quote this only because I have made a point to quote all the parts I disagree with, thereby agreeing with the other parts by implication, as long as they are interpreted according to my definitions. Obviously, I do not believe that earth and water “are not composed of other bodies”.

The primary elements, at the time of writing, seem to me to be the so-called “elementary particles”, as understood within the so-called “standard model of particle physics”; but I don’t really know or care what they are.

But, because every cause, as cause, is naturally prior to that which it causes, notice that we say a thing is prior in two ways, as Aristotle says in book XVI of the History of Animals(¶31)

This one is just strange. The History of Animals does not have a “book XVI”, and at any rate, why would it be the source for a claim about priority? The Categories defines four senses of priority; of those, he seems to have meant the first two, which best apply to a cause and its effect.

The rest of the treatise seems right, and I have nothing to say about it.

Saturday, April 2, 2022

Metaphysical commentaries

This is a list of my commentaries on various philosophical texts, which I wrote as a means to develop the opinions from my fundamental metaphysics.

While they will also be listed in the full list of posts, in this list I will write a short summary of what I do in each of them, so that my development is easier to track.

  • Fundamental metaphysics: Not a commentary. Defines being, non-being, matter, form, nothingness, final cause, formal cause, material cause, efficient cause.

  • Hume’s relations: Comments on Hume’s Treatise, §1.1.5. Defines relation, contrary opposition, contradictory opposition, difference in kind, difference in number.

  • Substance and accident: Comments on Hume’s Treatise, §1.1.6. Defines substance and accident.

  • Hume’s required medium: Comments on Hume’s Enquiry, §4. Elaborates on a priori reasoning about apparent motions.

  • Principles of nature: Comments on Thomas Aquinas’s De principiis naturæ. Explicitly defines act, potency, agent, privation, and element; gives new explanations of form and nothingness, which had already been defined. Implicitly defines generation, corruption, cause, principle, absolute necessity, conditional necessity, per se cause, per accidens cause, simple cause, composed cause.

  • Descartes’s confusions: Comments on the Discourse on the Method. Criticizes a misleading, ambiguous concept of “existence”.